Claus Michael Ringel: Pre-dinner Presentation at the BNU Conference on Representation Theory of Algebras, May 31, 2025.


German Fascination with Chinese Culture
in the 18th century:

The "Causa Wolffiana".


Christian Wolff
Oration 1721

This is a short report about the "Causa Wolffiana", a severe confrontation in the first half of the 18th century which was discussed throughout Europe.

It concerns Christian Wolff, a German mathematician and philosopher. He was an extraordinary polymath who lost in 1723 his university position at Halle and was expelled from Prussia for 17 years, due to a lecture he gave in 1721 with the title The practical religion of the Chinese, in which he outlined and praised the teaching of Confucius.

Everything what we write is of course well-known to the experts, however this knowledge is not at all widespread, neither in Germany or say in Europe, nor in China (often Chinese intellectuals are better informed about European affairs than the European themselves!). All details are easily available (one may look at Google or any other data base), even a written version of Wolff's lecture is available in print as a volume in the Philosophische Bibliothek published by Meiner (in Latin as well as translated into German), but one has to be aware of the case and to know the relevant keywords. Our aim is to draw the attention to the historic setting and to discuss its relevance. We can touch only the basic facts; for a deeper understanding of the controversy, the reader is refered to the literature.

1. Europe and China.

Before we report about Wolff himself, we want to draw the attention to the fact that Germany, or better the whole of Europe, was attracted in the 17th and 18th century by the Chinese culture. There was a burgeoning interest in chinoiseries, in decorative art, furniture, and architecture that imitates or is inspired by Chinese artistic traditions: Almost every castle tried to display Chinese porcelain, silk, tapestry, paravents. Chinese gardens became popular, with tea houses and pavillons.

Sanssouci: Tee House
Sanssouci: Dragon Pavillon
Berlin-Charlottenburg
Chinese porcelain

Since we deal with the European reception of Chinese ideas, we definitely have to refer to Leibniz. His volume Novissima Sinica (Latest news from China), published in 1697 and again in 1699, provided information about Chinese culture, society, and politics to a European audience. It was not only a collection of facts; it also was an attempt to foster cultural exchange and understanding between Europe and China. He believed that studying China could benefit Europe, particularly in areas like mathematics, philosophy, and governance. The book has a preface written by Leibniz, followed by a collection of reports and letters from Jesuit missionaries in China about Chinese history, philosophy, religion, and social customs.

The introduction of binary numbers is usually attributed to Leibniz. For example, the University at Hannover (named now after Leibniz), uses as its Logo his writing of the numbers 1, 2, 4 as the binary numbers 1, 10, 100 ... . One should be aware that apparently Leibniz was inspired by the Chinese trigrams used in the Yijing (易经). In this way, the binary number system which is the basis of all computer calculations, has obvious traces also to China.

 
Novissima Sinica
 
Binary numbers: Leibniz's writing
The eight trigrams

2. Leibniz, Wolff, Kant, Hegel.

Also, one should be aware of the main philosophers in Germany in the 18th century.

Leibniz
(1646 - 1716)
Wolff
(1679 - 1754)
Kant
(1724 - 1804)
Hegel
(1770 - 1831)

The names of Leibniz, Kant and Hegel are well-known to anyone. But Christian Wolff? Actually, his work was appreciated very much by his contemporaries. He was considered as a kind of student or follower of Leibniz and the socalled Leibniz-Wolff system dominated all the philosophical discussions in the mid of the 18th century in Germany and in many neighboring countries (we will say a little more about it, below).

Leibniz himself did not publish much. There is his Theodizee, published in 1710, all other works were published only after his death. For example, the Nouveaux Essays sur l'entendement humain was written 1703–05, but published in 1765. The Monadology, conceived at the end of the 17th century, was written 1714 for the Frech philosopher Nicolas François Rémond, and published in 1720. On the other hand, there were numerous letters which Leibniz wrote and where he outlined his ideas. Also Wolff got his information about Leibniz's thinking only via letters.

When Kant referred to the philosophical knowledge of his time, this was the Leibniz-Wolff philosophy. The aim of Kant was, to clarify the notions, to outline the underlying assumptions, and to arrange in this way a coherent doctrine. Note that the Newtonion physics starts with space and time as rigid data, being given independently of matter. Whereas Leibniz rated space and time as relation between material bodies, Kant gave them the status of an priori intuition, independent of empirical observations. In retrospect, one sees that Kant's vision is completely outdated - it was not at all an improvement, but a dead end!

The main target of our presentation is the time between Leibniz and Kant. Still, we have added above a (partly fading) picture of Hegel in order to draw the attention also to the further development. And again, in-between Kant and Hegel further names may be added, for example Johann Gotlieb Fichte (1762 - 1814). Whereas Leibniz, Wolff and Kant were mathematicians who were eager to use mathematical thinking as a fundamental tool to describe the world, this changed after Kant completely.

3. Christian Wolff: 1679 - 1754

From now on, let us focus the attention to Christian Wolff.

1679   born at Wroclaw (now Poland)
1699   student of mathematics, physics, and philosophy at Jena.
1703 lecturer at the university of Leipzig
1706 professor for mathematics (later also philosophy) at Halle (Saale), near to Leipzig.
 
Subjects: logic, mathematics, philosophy,
jurisprudence ("natural law")

He created a systematic approach to philosophy,
which later was called the "Leibniz-Wolff system"; some details will be mentioned below.
There were many followers, they were called the "Wolffianer".

Wolff was famous ry as a young man.
He became a member of all the relevant scientific academies:
 
1710   Member of the London Royal Society
1711   Member of Berliner Academie der Wissenschaften
1725   Honorary member of the St. Petersburg Academy
1733   Member of Academie de Sciences, Paris.
   

Wolff was, on the first hand, a mathematician:
        as a student, then as a teacher,
        (and I was informed by Jochen Ziegenbalg that the now standard calculation of π using the ideas of Archimedes, is due to Wolff).
But he soon extended his interest to various other subjects,
        both as a student, then as a teacher,
first, to physics, then to philosophy and psychology, and, very important, also to jurisprudence.

Here is a statement which he mentioned quite often;
it is also the first sentence of the Oration 1721 which is at the center of interest in my lecture:

Already as a child, I was eager to percieve the truth using only clear arguments,
so I started soon to analyse the methods of proofs used by mathematicians
and to transfer them to the philosophical disciplines.

4. The Leibniz-Wolff system

In general, in the 17th and the 18th century, there was a great tendency towards rationality:
to argue "in the manner of Euclid", to use "more geometrico".
This meant to work with axioms, with clear definitions. to deduce assertions from general principles and to accept no assertion whithout a proper proof.

Let me mention three corresponding texts from the 17th century:
  • Rene Descartes: Discours de la méthode, 1637.
  • Blaise Pascal: l'Esprit géométrique, 1658.
  • Baruch Spinoza: Ethica, ordine geometrico demonstrata, 1677.

This was also Wolff's intention, but he did not consider just an individual topic, his aim was to cover all subjects.

This then was labelled the Leibniz-Wolff system of knowledge

These were the topics which were discussed (the ordering followed partly the scholastic, or even Aristotelian tradition).

  • Logic.
  • Ontology.
  • Cosmology.
  • Rational psychology.
  • Theology.
  • Ethics.
  • Natural law.
  • Economic theory.
  • Society and politics.
  • Physics.
  • Mathematics.

5. Christian Wolff: his interest in China and the oration 1721

It was customary at that time that a rector or pro-rector when stepping down from this position
gave a public lecture on a topic which he considered to be of general interest.

In 1721, when Wolff stepped down as a pro-rector, he gave an oration with the title
Oratio de Sinarum Philosophia Practica - On the Practical Philosophy of the Chinese.
An expanded version of this oration was published by Wolff in 1726:

 

Wolff praised the purity of the moral precepts of Confucius,
pointing to them as an evidence of the power of human reason
to reach moral truth by its own efforts.

There was a lot of opposition at Halle, but Wolff continued to lecture about Chinese culture.

On 12 July 1723, Wolff held again a public lecture, this time at the end of his term as rector:
now comparing Moses, Christ, and Mohammed with Confucius.

Directly after his 1721 lecture, several professors of Halle had contacted the king of Prussia Friedrich Wilhelm I,
Wolff was accused of atheism.
Immediately after his 1723 lecture, Wolff was expelled from Prussia by Friedrich Wilhelm I
and his books were prohibited.
 
1723   Expulsion from Prussia:
to leave Prussian territory within 48 hours (or to be hanged).
His books were prohibited.

Some historians have rated this conflict (the "causa Wolffiana") as
- one of the most significant cultural confrontations of the 18th century, or even as
- the most important fight of the Enlightenment in Central Europe before the French Revolution.

As I have mentioned, Wolff was famous in Germany, even throughout Europe.
So immediately he got several offers and he decided to go to Marburg.

1723   Professor at Marburg

Wolff published the text of his oration in 1726.
A year before, there was an unauthorized publication of his lecture (in two editions), apparently by one of his enemies,
with hints insinuating that the Jesuits were supporting Wolff.
And shortly after his own publication, there was a further edition of the text, by Lange, one of his opponents at Halle,
with an outline of many objections.

Remark. I should add that Wolff's expulsion may have had also other reasons!
There were ongoing controversies between Wolff and a group of pietists at the University of Halle, the main opponents of Wolff were August Hermann Francke (1663 - 1727), the founder of the Francke Foundation (which still exists), as well as his former student Joachim Lange. These were the persons who informed the Prussian king about Wolff's lectures. They had complained also before about Wolff, starting in 1709, when Wolff enlarged the topics of his lectures and in this way attracted a lot of students. According to Voltaire, Francke had been teaching in an empty classroom, but Wolff attracted with his lectures around 1,000 students from all over.
And there were the usual university intrigues, say fights concerning the filling of positions.

Let me return to the scientific dispute!

6. The Chinese sources used by Wolff.

The four books: 四书, Sì Shū:
  • 大学   Dà Xué: The Great learning.
  • 中庸   Zhōng Yōng: Doctrine of the Mean
  • 论语   Lúnyŭ: Analects (speeches of Confucius)
  • 孟子   Mèngzĭ: Mencius.
And, in addition:
  • 孝經   Xiao Jing: this is a part of 十三經, Shisan jing.
  • 小学   Xiao Xué: an addition to Da Xué.

Wolff used translations by the Flemish missionaries François Noël (1651–1729) and Philippe Couplet (1623–1693).
Already in 1711, Wolff had published reviews of these books. Actually, these translations differ considerably. There is an interesting detail, which was discussed quite fiercely: whether "Tian" (天), heaven, may or could be translated as god. Why is there the title of the Chinese Emperor: "Tianzi" (天子), Son of the Heaven? And what means to venerate the heaven?

The published version of the 1721 oration contains a lot of annotations, some of them provide further information about China and its culture. There is a long discussion whether the Confucian thinking is atheistic or not: for being an atheist you should have knowledge about a god, but deny his power. And there are also references to Chinese buddhism, which is considered as really pagan, but also not relevant for Chinese thinking.

Wolff's conclusion, from his reading of Confucius:
The concept of "god" is not needed,
  • neither for an explanation of the world,
  • nor for establishing moral principles.
This may be considered as a decisive breakthrough in European philosophy.

Some hints about the development may be appropriate.

In Europe, theology was always a firm part of philosophy, it often is considered as one of the oldest academic disciplines. Plato opposed atheism, Aristotle discussed theology in his book Metaphysics. In the Middle Ages, philosophy was rated as just the handmaid of theology!

We have mentioned that the only treatise published by Leibniz is the Theodicy (1710), dealing with the acting of God, trying to resolve the problem of the existence of evil in the world. Here, we still have the dominance of theology.

On the other hand, in the second half of the 18th century, all religious beliefs were strongly criticized, for example in France by the Encyclopaedists, in England by Hume (1711 - 1776).

The assertion No god is needed should not be interpreted as a rejection of the idea of an existing god, neither for Wolff himself, nor for later philosophers and scientists. God may be seen either as a nice decoration of the world, or as a kind of target in the historical development (Hegel, Whitehead).

Nietzsche, in his work Die fröhliche Wissenschaft (1882) formulated the dictum God is dead. This was meant as a label not only for the loss of the belief in God, but for the decline of morality - in sharp contrast to Wolff!

7. The revocation of the expulsion in 1740

In 1740, King Friedrich Wilhelm I died and his oldest son was crowned as Friedrich II ("Friedrich the Great").
One of the first action of Friedrich II was to revoke the expulsion of Wolff.
 
1740   Revocation of Wolff's expulsion, Wolff became again professor at Halle

1740: Wolff's triumphant return to Halle
1743   Wolff became chancellor at the university of Halle.
1754   Wolff died at Halle (Saale)

A side remark. In the plot we have presented, king Friedrich Wilhelm I is seen as the rogue, his son king Friedrich II as the savior, and this corresponds well to a quite standard assessment of both. FW I got the (pejorative) nickname "Soldatenkönig" (Soldier King), whereas Friedrich II is usually called "The Great".

However:
a proper evaluation of the respective merits may lead to a quite different evaluation!
Of course, FW I built up a huge Prussian army (and this definitely was the start of the awful Prussian hybris), but he himself never fought any war, whereas F II started wars from his first days of reigning, unjustified ones, violant, brutal... (apparently, this impressed the further generations, so they called him "The Great").
FW I initiated many reforms and cared about public welfare. He was modest and economical, he tried to confine corruption and inefficiency in government. In contrast, F II used the state fortune saved by his father to pamper his brothers and sisters.
Was F II an esthete? Yes, he played music, wanted to be recognised as a philosopher, copied French customs. On the other hand, he was completely ignorant of the awakening of the German literature and culture during his reign.
He was a misanthrope who wanted to be burried with his dogs.
(And we should add that attemps to rehabilitate Wolff started already in 1733, thus several years before the death of FW I. In particular, the ban of the books of Wolff was cancelled in 1734.)

8. Jesuits and Pietists

Let me also add a remark on the religious background of the fight between Wolff and Francke.

One should be aware that Europe is no longer religious, still old religious fights are virulant:

There is the old fight between catholics and protestants, here: between Jesuits and Pietists.
The China mission was organized by Jesuits, the Pietists were active in India.
(Leibniz and Wolff both were protestant, but they strongly relied on the Jesuit reports from China).

The missionaries wanted to spread Christianity all over the world.
On the other hand, they informed about the local cultures,
sometimes definitely on eye level.

The pietists are now considered as old-fashioned, as outmoded
(for example, in America, they deny the achievements of modern natural sciences).
However, the pietists in the 17th and 18th century were strongly engaged
in spreading the modern knowledge!

And I want to stress: Both pietists and Jesuits focussed their attention to education!
(and, in this way, they are comparable to Confucius).

In particular, the modern secondary school movement in the West strongly relies on pietistic ideas: in contrast to the classical secondary schools which were based on the teaching of Greek and Latin, there now was the a focus on training in basic subjects, in particular also mechanical skills such as woodworking and domestic skills.

The most important contribution by Francke was his Orphant School at Halle:
to educate orphants not just to survive, but to be able to understand the world.
One still can admire Francke's Chamber of Wonders, a collection of artifacts from all over the world, which were used for the teaching. It ressembles the collections in the Renaissance and Baroque castles used by dukes in order to impress and surprise their visitors. But the Francke collection was not meant for noblemen, but for the orphants he took care of.

Chamber of Wonders at Halle


Afterthoughts

1.   The European period which we have discussed here is called the Age of Enlightenment.
Kant's treatise Answering the Question: What Is Enlightenment? formulates: Enlightenment is man's leaving his self-imposed immaturity. In this way, he stressed the demand: Sapere aude! - Have courage to use your own reason. And precisely this Sapere aude! was the motto of the Societas Alethophilorum (Society of Lovers of Truth), founded in 1734 by some followers of Wolff, in order to support his rehabilitation. The society used a medaillon showing Minerva on one side, with Leibniz and Wolff on the back.

2.   In 2011, the National Museum of China presented a large exhibition on the European Age of Enlightment,
accompanied by several panels which brought together German and Chinese philosophers and scientists. There was a famous controversy between Wolf Lepenies and Gan Yang. Wolf Lepenies tried to propagate the reading of Kant, he claimed that Kant's thinking never was accepted in China. In contrast, Gan Yang (甘陽) stressed that Enlightenment means: to overcome superstition - and he pointed to three periods:
  •   the superstition, in ancient times, given by mythology,
  •   then, later the superstition given by religion,
  •   and now, the superstition, given by glorifying Western ideas.
Apparently, the positions of Lepenies and Gan were not really the basis for a fruitful dialogue!

3.   Clearly, there are several experts in China who have read and who know Kant very well. In 2011, the taz, a German daily newspaper (at that time, before the corona crisis, not yet a kind of govermental bulletin) published an interview with Huang Liaoyu (黄燎宇) from Beijing University with the titel: Kant didn't dare ("Kant hat sich nicht getraut"). He points out that whereas Kant was propagating the right to critizise everything, he himself did not dare to critizise the Prussion government or the Prussian king. It may be also of interest that at the end of the interview, he comments on the huge Confucius statue which was temporarily errected so that one could look at the same time at Confucius and at the Mao portrait at the Tiananmen Gate: a witty combination! No one in China will be disturbed in this way, but the foreigners.

4.   Two years ago, in May 2023, Huang Liaoyu published a rather depressing account about the present relationship between Germany and China (mainly based on the scientific contacts in the humanities), ending with a plea to recover the former fruitful exchange of ideas.

Let me dedicate this text to Professor Liu ShaoXue who visited 40 years ago Germany and other European countries in order to start our cooperation. As all of you know, this endeavor has been and still is really successful.



Some references

  • Wolff, Christian: Rede über die praktische Philosophie der Chinesen. Lateinisch-Deutsch. Felix Meiner Verlag. (1985)
  • Wolff, Christian: Gesammelte Werke. Hrg. Jean École, Hans Werner Arndt, u.a.. Olms Verlag, starting 1962.
  • Theis, Robert and Aichele, Alexander (Hrsg): Handbuch Christian Wolff. Springer Verlag (2018).

  • Chin Annping: Konfuzius - Geschichte seines Lebens. Verlag der Weltreligionen. (2009).
  • Corr, Charles A.: Christian Wolff and Leibniz. Journal of the History of Ideas. University of Pennsylvania Press. Vol. 36 (2). (1975)
  • Delekat, Friedrich: Immanuel Kant. Quelle & Meyer. (1963).
  • Godazgar, Ines: Große Namen: Christian Wolff. Campus Hallensis (2019).
    https://www.campus-halensis.de/artikel/grosse-namen-christian-wolff/
  • Göse, Franz: Friedrich Wilhelm I. Die vielen Gesichter des Soldatenkönigs. wbg-Theis (2020).
  • Israel, Jonathan I.: Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity. 1650-1759. Oxford University Press. (2002).
  • Knüppel, Michael: Christian Wolffs chinesische Ketzereien. In: Die Mark Brandenburg. Verlag für Regional- und Zeitgeschichte. (2021)
  • Die Lehren des Konfuzius. Die vier kanonischen Bücher. Chinesisch und Deutsch. Übersetzt und erkäutert von Richard Wilhelm. Vorwort: Hans von Ess. Zweitausend
  • Lee, Eun-jeung. Kant zu China und Konfuzius. In: Dialektik: Zeitschrift für Kulturphilosophie ; Nr. 1 (2002).
    https://www.e-aoi.uzh.ch/apps/china-west/documents/16755
  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm: Novissima Sinica (1607). Das Neueste von China. Nachdruck. Iudicium Verlag (1979)
  • Lepenies, Wolf: Kant kam nicht bis China. Die Welt. (2012).
    https://www.welt.de/print/die_welt/politik/article13822533/Kant-kam-nicht-bis-China.html
  • Li Wenchao and Poser, Hans (Hrsg): Das Neueste über China. G.W. Leibnzens Novissima Sinica von 1697, Franz Steiner Verlag (2000).
  • Huang Liaoyu: Kant hat sich nicht getraut. taz (2011).
    https://taz.de/Chinesischer-Germanist-ueber-Aufklaerung/!5123895/
  • Huang Liaoyu: Der Adler und der Drache: Plädoyer für die deutsch-chinesische Freundschaft. Tagesspiegel, 25.05.2023. https://www.tagesspiegel.de/kultur/der-adler-und-der-drache-pladoyer-fur-die-deutsch-chinesische-freundschaft-9846683.html
  • Wallmann, Johannses: Der Pietismus. Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht (2005).
  • Wikipedia. Various entries.
  • Jochen Ziegenbalg: Algorithmen − von Hammurapi bis Gödel. Springer. 4th edition, 2016.